Plato and the goodness of the body. Part 7. Phaedrus and the fall of the soul into embodiment
c) The Phaedrus and the fall of the soul into embodiment
Plato’s myth in the Phaedrus
of the soul as a charioteer with two winged horses (246a–257b) seems, at face
value, to have a drastically negative view of human embodiment. We see here the
tripartite view of the soul introduced earlier in this series. The soul is “the
natural union of a team of winged horses and their charioteer” (246a). The
charioteer is the intellect, the obedient horse is spirit, and the unruly horse
is appetite. The soul is not one part of this, such as the charioteer, but the
whole team.
In the myth we first see the gods, who are also
charioteers with winged horses, though in their case both horses are noble and
in perfect balance. They gods
effortlessly ascend to the rim of heaven to look “beyond” it to contemplate the
forms. Human souls try to follow in their train, but with their unruly dark
horses this is a difficult ascent as the bad horse seeks to drag the soul down.
Some manage to get just high enough to glimpse the forms, others rise and fall,
glimpsing some forms and missing others, many don’t get high enough to see
anything. The soul that glimpses the forms gets another safe circuit around the
heavens. In theory, it can keep this up forever (248c). However, if it fails to
see the forms it starts to forget, is “weighed down, sheds its wings, and falls
to earth” (248c). Depending on how much a person saw before he fell, he will be
anything from a philosopher all the way down to a tyrant, the lowest form of
human in Plato’s view (248e). The goal is to grow one’s wings back and ascend again.
This takes a long time and is very difficult. What makes it so hard is that
“the senses are so murky that it is only a few people who are able to make out,
with difficulty, the original of the likeness they encounter here,” unlike when
we were perceiving the forms apart from our senses. “That was the ultimate
vision, and we saw it in pure light because we were pure ourselves, not buried
in this thing we are carrying around now, which we call a body, locked in like
an oyster in its shell” (250b-c).
The picture of an undesirable “fall” of
humanity into a body, a body in which it is now buried alive and imprisoned, is
hardly imagery that presents a positive view of embodiment. It is no wonder
that many have balked at it. However, I would like to tentatively suggest that things
may not be as they appear at first blush.
First, we should note that what Plato offers is
“a mythic hymn” (265c) that tells us not “what a soul actually is” but “what it is like,” the former being a task for a god, the latter being humanly
possible (246a). The non-literal aspects of the ascent are hinted at in talk of
the “the place beyond heaven . . . without colour and without shape and without
solidity” (247c). This cannot be a literal “place” nor can it be literally
“beyond” heaven. It is “visible only to intelligence” (247c); an intellectual
“space” that occupies no physical space. So we need to be careful how we
interpret the myth.
Second, we should note a major problem with
taking the story as relating to an actual fall into embodiment from a blissful
disembodied state. The soul under discussion in the “story-like hymn” is the
tripartite soul known from various other Platonic texts. The problem is that everywhere else in Plato the spirit and
appetite (the two horses) are extensions of the soul under the conditions of embodiment.[1]
To take the story even semi-literally would be to see pre-embodied souls as tripartite and this is problematic at two
levels. First, it is inconsistent with what Plato says elsewhere. Second, and
more importantly, it is difficult to give any worthwhile account of the two
horses for a disembodied soul. Consider how Socrates explains the nature of the
dark, unruly horse: it is attracted with passion for earthly things and drags
the soul down (247b); it hungers for physical bodily pleasures (253e–254a).
Surely these are the passions of the embodied soul.
Now it may be objected that the notion of
disembodied tripartite souls must be intelligible because the gods themselves
are here tripartite. They too are charioteers with pairs of winged horses. But
we need to remember that for Plato the gods are not disembodied. The Timaeus
makes very clear that the gods are astral deities composed of soul and body. Their bodies are those astral objects
that moved in perfect circles around the heavens (Tim. 38c–40d). Because nothing disturbs their circular motions they
are closer to perfection. This, presumably, is why the myth in Phaedrus images them as having two white
horses in perfect union (246a; 247b). Humans, in the Timaeus, have their circular motions interrupted by the rectilinear
motions of up, down, left, right, backwards, and forwards.[2]
This is a result of embodiment and it generates disruption and problems for
reason. The Phaedrus myth pictures
this condition as that of having an untamed horse that struggles against the
wishes of the charioteer. Now if this parallel between the analysis of the
internal conflict within the human soul in Phaedrus
and Timaeus is correct, then the soul
we are talking about is embodied in both
cases. What I am suggesting is that while Plato is telling a story about a fall into embodiment, we need to appreciate
that it is a story and be open to the
real possibility that he is not making any claims about the biography of any
actual souls. He is not, in other words, speaking of an actual or literal fall
into embodiment, but of the metaphorical
fall of an already-embodied subject.[3]
Third, let’s consider the main point of the
myth, the problem created by embodiment is, as we saw in the Phaedo, a very specific problem—an epistemological problem. The contrast throughout
the myth is between the pure sight on reality when considered apart from the
senses and the very murky view offered by the bodily senses (250b). The focus
of the myth is on a fall from a higher mode of apprehending reality to a lower mode.
For nourishment the fallen souls have “their own opinions” instead of knowledge
(248b). The wings are fed from the grass of the plain where truth stands, and
cannot be sustained by mere “opinion.” So the task of the soul is to re-grow
its wings and to ascend again, moving from sense perception to apprehension of
the forms. But, like the descent, this ascent is an epistemic one symbolized as an ascent from the body.
Fourth, the surprise, in light of the use of
rather negative body imagery in the myth, is that the actual journey of ascent
grants an important role for the body. The philosopher sees beauty here in the
sensible world (for beauty is seen all around us) and is “reminded” of the
vision of beauty itself. This beauty captures his heart and makes him seem to
others like a mad man, for he is “possessed by a god” (249d). The perceivers of
beauty “are startled when they see an image of what they saw up there. Then
they are beside themselves, and their experience is beyond comprehension
because they cannot fully grasp what it is they are seeing” (250a). So literal vision, “the clearest of our
senses” (250d), is the start of the journey. Radiant beauty sparkles through
the eyes and the intellect recognizes in it that by which the beautiful
particular is beautiful, and the wings start to grow.
Importantly, the ascent does not mean leaving the particular
beautiful thing/person behind. The philosopher becomes obsessed with the
particular object of his love (in the Phaedrus,
it is a beautiful boy[4]) and must keep on gazing at it or recalling it in
order for his wings to keep growing (251d-e). Ascending to beauty itself does
not require leaving the beautiful particular behind.
As
well as demonstrating that Plato did not
wish to drive a wedge between form and appearance, the strongly positive view
of methexis (participation) in the Phaedrus frees him from the charge of
otherworldliness and total withdrawal from physicality, for the philosophic
ascent does not result in a “loss” of love for particular beautiful things,
since the particular participates in beauty itself. Thus the philosopher is
synonymous with the lover of beauty, and also with one of a musical or loving
nature (248d). . . . [I]t is precisely within the physical world that
he recognizes a likeness to the realities, and then is ‘stricken with amazement
and cannot control himself’ (241a). . . . [T]he image of the good in
the beauty of physicality is not just an empty ‘version’ or simulacrum.[5]
And so if the philosopher can be accused of neglecting ‘things below’ like the
insane bird (249d), it is not that he turns away from physicality itself (for
that would deny him access to the good), but that he neglects a mundane apprehension of physicality as
merely immanent or crudely separated from the whole, and all the concomitant proprieties
of property, custom, and conventional status (252a). By contrast the contagion
of the divine urges the philosopher from place to place, yearning to see the
beautiful again.[6]
Furthermore, when the object of his love is
another person, as it is in the Phaedrus,
the true lover seeks to lead the beloved on the same journey for the beloved’s
own sake, rather than using them as a means to an end (255b-e).[7]
This is the kind of love that Socrates praises and seeks to awaken in young
Phaedrus (252b). And it is praise of this love that is the whole point of
Socrates’ speech. Eros, he says, is
sent by the gods for our benefit
(244a).
Fifth, the two horses themselves play an
interesting role in the journey. On the one hand, the unruly horse can cause
major problems, forcefully resisting the directions of the charioteer and the
promptings of his partner horse. He can drag a soul down into being entombed in
a body, blind to reality. However, on the other, the image itself suggests that
the horses play a key role in motivating and moving the soul.[8]
The charioteer (intellect) is to give direction, but the horses are to
translate this direction into movement. As Martha Nussbaum observes, “If we
starve and suppress emotions and appetites, it may well be at the cost of so
weakening the entire personality that it will be unable to act decisively;
perhaps it will cease to act altogether. The idea of ‘nourishing’ the
non-intellectual plays an important part in Plato’s myth.”[9]
Of course, the horses need training and taming, but when they are so
disciplined they play a constructive rather than a destructive role. More than
that, Nussbaum argues that the horses play a positive role in guiding our
aspirations towards understanding. Socrates’ hymn of praise to the divine madness
of erotic love makes very clear that “certain sorts of essential and high
insights come to us only through the guidance
of the passions. . . . The non-intellectual elements have a keen
natural responsiveness to beauty, especially when beauty is presented through
the sense of sight.”[10] The three
aspects of soul, each with its own desires, respond to beauty in different
ways. The appetite wants to have sex with the beautiful boy (254a) while the
spirit feels shame and holds back (254a). This conflicted reaction to an
instance of beauty throws the charioteer into an initial state of confusion
until “his memory is carried back to the nature of beauty” (254b). In this way,
the horses, in their limited perceptions of beauty, can spark the mind to seek
the form of beauty itself. The dark horse can be overpowered by the charioteer
and trained to know fear, awe, and respect in the presence of the beautiful
boy. So, when rightly aligned, the embodied parts of the soul can guide and
drive the philosopher towards the world so that he is enabled to ascend to the forms.[11]
The point is that while the body can
be an epistemic tomb, it need not be.
The body can play a constructive role in the pursuit of reality so long as it
knows its place vis-à-vis the charioteer.
Plato’s problem is not with bodies per se, but
with disordered souls. The reordering of the soul and the regrowth of its wings
does not require disembodiment. Remember that it is the whole soul that is winged (246a). The soul that falls and the soul
that regrows its wings and ascends to the forms is the tripartite soul (nous, spirit, and appetite), which is the embodied soul.
[1] This
is the case in texts apparently earlier (e.g., Republic) and later (e.g., Timaeus)
than the Phaedrus. So it is hard to
think that Plato changed his mind on the matter. On the link between
tripartation and embodiment in the Timaeus
see Johansen, Plato’s Natural Philosophy,
142–52.
[2] See fn. 38.
[3] Eric Perl
suggests a very similar reading of the myth in Thinking Being, ch. 2, section 5. In further support of the reading
he observes that later in the dialogue Socrates says that when he observes a
person who is able to rightly discern forms he will “follow behind as if he
[the enlightened person] were a god” (266b). This is an allusion to the myth in
which the “pre-incarnate” souls “follow a god” to “the place above the heavens.”
Perl’s point is that the story is a mythic presentation of this same point. It does not require literal disembodiment. Thus, one need not take the myth at face
value.
[4] The context of
the dialogue is the warped homoerotic relationship between Lysias and Phaedrus.
Phedrus is obsessed with Lysias, but Lysias merely uses Phaedrus for his own
ends. Socrates presents himself, in contrast to Lysias, as a true lover of
Phaedrus, a philosophical lover who seeks Phaedrus’ own betterment. On this
theme see Bradley, Who Is Phaedrus?
[5] Cf. “[W]hen
Plato says that sensible objects are only imperfectly beautiful or just, he
does not mean that they are approximately
beautiful or just [as if they were imperfect copies of a perfect exemplar].
Rather, he means that they are only
accidentally beautiful or just, while the Form and its characters possess
the relevant property in an essential manner.” Alexander Nehamas, “The
Imperfection of the Sensible World,” 178. Nehemas, however, does still conceive
of forms as perfect models. His point is that particulars can (for a time)
possess the relevant properties perfectly, and thus be truly good or just or
wise or beautiful. Their imperfection lies in that they, unlike the form, do
not possess the properties essentially.
Indeed, following Allan Silvermann, I think that Plato does not believe that
particulars possess any properties
essentially, but only by participation in forms. In other words, particulars,
unlike forms, do not have an essence.
It is worth
saying that while forms self-predicate, it is not agreed what such
self-predication amounts to in Plato. So the claim that “the beautiful (i.e.,
the form of beauty) is beautiful” can mean that it is supremely beautiful—the
perfect model of beauty—or that it is self-identical (i.e., it is itself and
nothing else). Following Silvermann, I understand self-predication in the later
sense. “Beauty is beautiful” does not mean that beauty is a beautiful object.
Rather, each form self-predicates insofar as each form is its essence. “When Plato says that each Form is itself
by itself, auto kath auto, monoeides, simple, eilikrines, pure, and one, I take him to be referring only to the
relation of Form to essence. Being is found only where subject and essence are
related, that is only where essence is predicated of some subject. . . .
[S]ince the only thing that [a Form] Is is its essence, each Form is monoeides, ‘of one essence’” (Dialectic of Essence, 91).
[6]
Catherine Pickstock, After Writing: On
the Liturgical Consummation of Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 14,
15.
[7] See fn. 53.
[8] In
this analogy Plato clearly sees each of the three “parts” as a source of desire
within the soul, each with its own object (the charioteer, nous, desires “the plain truth,” the white horse, spirit, is a
lover of honour, the black horse, appetite, loves sexual pleasure and
gratification). The challenge is to bring these desires into harmony under the
rule of the charioteer.
[9] Nussbaum, “This
Story Isn’t True,” 214.
[11] Against
this positive evaluation of the horses in Phaedrus,
see Frisbee Sheffield, “Erôs Before
and After Tripartation,” in Rachel Barney et al. (eds.), Plato and the Divided Self, 211–37.
Comments