Plato and the goodness of the body. Part 2. Forms, embodiment, and particularity
I. Forms, Embodiment, and Particularity
We need in this context to consider Plato’s famous (or infamous) notion
of forms.[1]
His critics often see his alleged anti-body views as inextricably tied up with
his ideas about forms. Plato, we are told, aspired to get away from the body
and to escape into the timeless, spaceless world of ideals. In this way he
disparaged the world of the senses and of bodies and longed for the perfect, disembodied
world. But is this really what Plato thought? I shall argue that it is a
misleading caricature of his philosophy.
The words translated as “form,” eidos and idea, relate to the appearance
of something to an observer’s gaze. For different particulars to have the same
“form”—to be beautiful or to be wise, say—is for them to have a common
appearance, for different things to convey the same idea to an observer.[2]
Forms are the intellectual paradigms and patterns that make particulars what
they are—that enable them to be anything at all, that give them their identity.
“Far from stripping the sensible world of all intelligibility and locating it
‘elsewhere,’ Plato expressly presents the forms as the truth, the whatness, the
intelligibility, and hence the reality, of
the world.”[3]
They are what Eric Perl calls “ideas-in-things”—that in things which can also
be present in thought.[4]
In Plato’s thinking, to deny forms would be to estrange thought and being and
hence to deny the possibility of thinking or speaking about anything in the
world (Parmenides 135b-c).
Now Plato is very clear that forms are “separate”
from their instances. This has misled many to think that Plato imagines them
existing in another realm, a higher world that is better than this cruddy sensory
world. This is arguably to misunderstand the notion of separation (chôrismos). Clearly, if one considers a
range of particulars that all share the same form, that form must be distinct
from, must transcend, any of its instances (Meno
74b-e). A just ruler, for instance, cannot be justice itself.
Forms are intelligible appearances that are
“perceived” by thought, not by sight. You can see sensory particulars but not
forms—you can see the just ruler but you cannot see justice itself, you can see
a healthy dog but you cannot see health itself (Phaedo 65d-66a, 74a-b). “Forms are ideas, not in the sense of
concepts or abstractions, but in that they are realities apprehended by thought
rather than by sense. They are thus ‘separate’ in that they are not additional
members of the world of sensible things, but are known by a different mode of
awareness. But this does not mean that they are ‘located elsewhere,’ or that they
are not, as Plato says, the very intelligible contents, the truth and reality of sensible things.”[5]
“[T]he sensible beauty we perceive in things is the intelligible form of beauty
manifest in time and space; in other words, it is to say that sense experience
is the expression of a meaning . . .
.”[6]
Some propose that Plato thought of forms as
perfect models that particulars copy. Now forms understood as perfect models
are open to the so-called “third man” objection[7]
made famous by Aristotle,[8]
but already anticipated by Plato himself in the Parmenides (132c–133a). However, arguably Plato did not conceive of
forms in this way and used the Parmenides
to shoot down that way of interpreting his notion of forms.[9]
It is better to think of forms as like a recipe. “The information that the
chocolate cake about to be served has been made in accordance with a certain
recipe does not leave us expecting the cake to be a copy, likeness, image,
representation, reproduction, imitation, or semblance of the recipe.”[10]
Forms are what Plato calls paradigms (paradeigmata),
in the sense of being intelligible patterns (Euthyphro 6e). Such patterns are not discernable with the sense
perceptions but with the mind, for they are pure idea, pure thought-content.
But these intelligible patterns show up in particular sensory objects as their
intelligible structure—that by virtue of which the particulars are what they
are.
So here is a fundamental tension that Plato
works hard to maintain: the intelligible pattern that is a form can be seen in particulars, but if the pattern is
considered “itself by itself”[11]
then we must acknowledge that it cannot be reduced to any particular. Forms are
both immanent in the sensory world but also transcend it. Forms considered
apart from their instances are separate, not in that they exist in another world,
but in that they are of a different ontological order.[12]
“Where among all the beautiful things in this world, is beauty? Everywhere and
nowhere: everywhere, because wherever a beautiful thing is, there is beauty, as
a property which it has and by which it is beautiful; nowhere, because we
cannot point to any one of them and say, ‘There it is!’ as if it were identical
with or confined to that one instance.”[13]
Beauty is thus both immanent and transcendent. Transcendence is not to be
confused with being somewhere else, except in a metaphorical sense. The forms
are “in” the sensible world but not “of” it, not objects in addition to oranges
and monkeys and ice skates. Thus, the world of sensibles, by virtue of its intelligible
structures, points “beyond” itself to the forms in which it participates: “it
is by the beautiful that all beautiful things are beautiful” (Phaedo 100e). This is what is sometimes
referred to as a participatory ontology in which the world of the senses is
utterly dependent on and “suspended from” a more fundamental reality.[14]
The key thing is this: the forms are not
somewhere else, in another world that we need to go to. The forms are in their instances, but cannot ever be
reduced to those instances.[15]
They ever transcend each and every particular. Therefore, a beautiful river really is beautiful; a just city really is just; a good ruler really is good.[16] This immediately shows us that those
who claim that Plato thought of the sensory world as somehow bad or evil are
way off track! On the contrary, it was good and beautiful.
It is a mistake to infer from the fact that
Plato considers the forms to be “real”[17]
that the world of the senses is irreal or illusory. The ontological status of
particulars is that of being in between
being and non-being, something and nothing (Republic
478d). For Plato reality (which he identifies with intelligibility) is not
something that is only “on” or “off,” but something that comes in degrees.[18]
Forms, as pure intelligibles, are completely real; particular sensory things
have reality to the extent that they participate in forms.[19]
The dialogues often speak of the ascent of the
soul to the forms, but these ascents need to be understood as epistemic ascents—the “ascent of the
mind” (Rep. 517b)—not as literal
ascents out of our world into another, spiritual world.[20]
They are, rather, cognitive ascents from one way of apprehending the world
(through the senses) to another (through the intellect), from appearance to
reality. These cognitive states come with “degrees of clarity, corresponding to
the degree of truth possessed by their subject-matter” (Rep. 511e). That this is so can be seen in the famous divided line
illustration from the Republic (509d–511e).
Epistemic
mode:
Four “states of mind” (pathêmata) |
|
Focus
of the soul
|
||
Knowledge (episteme)
|
dialectic (noesis):
thinking which is “through forms, to forms, and finishes with forms”
|
L4
|
The Good
+
forms
|
Intelligible reality
|
reasoning (dianoia),
towards forms from sensible objects
|
L3
|
|||
Opinion (doxa)
|
trust (pistis)
|
L2
|
sensible objects (natural and manufactured)
|
The visible image of intelligible reality
|
Imagination/guesswork/illusion
(eikasia)
|
L1
|
images of sensible objects
(e.g., reflections and shadows)
|
The divided line is built around the picture of
reality and its image. Socrates starts with the relation between objects in the
sensible world (L2) and dim images of them (L1)—reflections in water or
polished surfaces, or shadows. This becomes the paradigm for the relation
between the sensible “realm” (L1–L2) and the intelligible “realm” (L3–L4): the
world we see around us is a dim reflection of a more real world. It is a
shadowland. So ontologically speaking
the direction is down, from reality to image—from the Good to the forms to the
particulars, their images. But epistemically
speaking we need to proceed backwards, from image to reality (from L2 to L3
to L4).
“Despite its divisions, the Line represents the
integrity of the Whole . . . : the intelligible and visible domains
are now depicted as parts of one and the
same line. . . . Plato emphasizes the interconnectedness of all
levels of human experience.”[21]
We have a single reality, a single
line (L1–L4), which can be divided according to different modes of
perception—two modes of sensory perception and two modes of intellectual
perception. The ascent up the line (from L1 to L4) is an ascent described in
terms of different modes of perceiving.[22]
The physical world that we can see is “nothing but meaning made tangible.”[23]
To understand the perceptible world aright one must understand it in terms of the
higher reality in which it participates and which enables it to be. To do that one must be able to
ascend in one’s mind from the ever-shifting sensible world of perceptions—what
we see and hear—to perceive the forms “themselves by themselves.” To ascend
from seeing beauty, say, in this or that particular thing to seeing “beauty itself.”[24]
This philosophical ascent is presented as a separation of soul and body; an
indifference to the body and its needs, as far as that is possible (Phaedo 64c–65a; 67c-d). This, according
to the simile of the cave, is the painful, disorientating, and prolongued
cognitive journey of moving beyond the particular instances (perceived by the
body) to the universal forms (perceived by the soul). Having done this we are
enabled to return to this sensory world seeing it and understanding it afresh,
better able to live with wisdom and in tune with the nature of reality. Here is
how Socrates describes the return of the philosopher to the cave: “You must
therefore each descend in turn and live with your fellows in the cave and get
used to seeing in the dark; once you get used to it you will see a thousand
times better than they [the prisoners, who have never been outside the cave] do
and will distinguish the various shadows, and know what they are shadows of,
because you have seen the truth about things admirable and just and good” (Rep. 520c).
Must one die to see the forms aright? From the Phaedo one may suspect so (66d–67a).
However, the Republic suggests
otherwise. With many years of hard training, the philosopher rulers of the Republic are said to be able to achieve
knowledge of the forms, even of the Good,[25]
while fully embodied. Indeed, it is
precisely this perception of reality that enables them to be good and wise
rulers on their return to the cave, able to discern which actions are truly
courageous, temperate, and the like (Republic
484c-d; 500d; 519c–520e; 540a-b).
So Plato’s theory of forms does not provide any
basis for despising embodiment. Indeed, it can be construed in such a way as to
provide the very basis upon which the value of the body can be established.
[1] For a general
introduction to the theory of forms and the difficult interpretative issues
involved, see T. H. Irwin, “The Theory of Forms,” in Gail Fine (ed.), Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999) 143–70. For the idea that we can trace
a clear line of development from early dialogues with a Socratic interest in
definitions towards middle-period dialogues with a distinctively Platonic
interest in forms (with the Meno and
a hinge text between the two phases) see R. M. Dancy, “Platonic Definitions and
Forms,” in Hugh H. Benson (ed.), A
Companion to Plato (Oxford: Blackwell, 2009), 70–84; Allan Silverman, The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato’s
Metaphysics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009). Be that as it may,
the later Platonic thought is a clear and continuous development from the
earlier Socratic project.
[2] My
basic anti-two-worlds-interpretation of Plato is heavily shaped by the work of
Eric Perl. See, for instance, “The Presence of the Paradigm: Immanence and
Transcendence in Plato’s Theory of Forms” The
Review of Metaphysics 53.2 (1999) 339–62; Perl, Thinking Being: Introduction to Metaphysics in the Classical Tradition
(Leiden: Brill, 2014), ch. 2. “What Plato presents in the middle dialogues,
then, is not two worlds, a world of sensible instances on the one hand and a
world of transcendent forms on the other, but rather one world, that of
intelligible form, and the appearances of that world which constitute
sensibles” (Perl, “Presence of the Paradigm,” 351).
[3]
Perl, Thinking Being, ch. 2.
[4]
Forms are “in” (en) (Euth. 5d; Lach.191e, 192a) or “through” (dia)
(Lach. 192c; Meno 74a) or “occupy, fill” (kataschê)
(Phd. 104d) their instances. Plato
can also speak of the communion (koinônia)
of forms and particulars or the “presence” (parousia)
of forms in things (Phd. 100d).
[5]
Perl, Thinking Being, no pages.
[6] D.
C. Schindler, The Catholicity of Reason
(Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2013), 125.
[7] The
basic idea is that if a particular (e.g., a particular man, Socrates) is
explained in terms of reflecting a perfect, non-sensory particular (the form of
man) then we have a problem. This is because the form of man is itself a
particular man and one must then ask how to explain the particular form, and
one must postulate a form behind the form (a third man). But this, of course,
sets us into an infinite regress of forms and we discover that we have
explained nothing at all. On the much discussed third man arguments see, for
instance, S. Marc Cohen, “The Logic of the Third Man,” in Gail Fine (ed.),
Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology,
275–97; All this said, the notion of forms-as-perfect-models can be configured
to get around third man objections. On which see Sarah Broadie, Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 74–75. But this is not relevant
to us, because we are not thinking of forms in this way.
[8] See Gail
Fine, On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of
Plato’s Theory of Forms (Oxford: Clarendon, 1993), 217–32.
[9]
This is how I am strongly inclined to understand the perplexing text of the Parmenides. Plato’s language does
sometimes suggests the notion of forms are ideal, non-sensible particulars. For
instance, particulars may be spoken of as “images” of forms. However, we must
note that for Plato an image is not the same as a copy (Crat. 432b-d).
For
a very helpful guide to the exceptionally difficult text of the Parmenides, see Arnold Hermann, Plato’s Parmenides: Text, Translation, and
Introductory Essay. Translation in collaboration with Sylvana
Chrysakopoulou (Las Vegas: Parmenides, 2010).
[10]
Broadie, Nature and Divinity, 62.
[11] Phd. 66a; 78d; Symp. 211b; Parm. 129d.
[12] Forms,
unlike particulars, are timeless and changeless (Phd. 78d-80b; Rep. 479a,
e; 484b; 500c; Tim. 28a). However, as
Stephen Clark notes, this distinction is helpful: “If ‘Beauty’ were only what
we have so far seen as beautiful, worship would be the kind of conservatism
beloved of bureaucrats: that nothing be allowed to change. It is because
Platonism does not equate Beauty with particular beauties that we can be
reassured: change need not be an evil, because Beauty is realized in
indefinitely (infinitely?) many ways.” S. R. L. Clark, How to Think about the Earth: Philosophical
and Theological Models for Ecology (London: Mowbray, 1993), 66.
[13]
Perl, “The Presence of the Paradigm,” 344.
[14]
Alternatively: “I suppose that if I had to give a kind of portmanteau name to
the view of things I find most convincing, it would be the ‘metaphysics of
eminence’—borrowing the scholastic notion that the lower reality is always
‘more eminently’ or ‘virtually’ contained in the higher realities, while the
higher is participated in and expressed by the lower. . . .
[B]eautiful things are caused by, among other things, transcendent beauty.
Whatever one calls it, however, and however dependent it is on the clearly
inadequate spatial metaphors of the above and the below, it is a vision of
reality in which the higher is not the epiphenomenal and largely illusory
residue of the lower—down there where reality is really real, as it were—but a
causal order in its own right, comprising the forms and ends and rational
harmonies that shape and guide and explain the world. Then, beyond all those
forms of causality, comprehending, transcending, pervading, underlying, and
creating them, is that which is highest and most eminent of all, the boundless
source of all reality, the infinity of being, consciousness, and bliss that is
God.” David Bentley Hart, The Experience
of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss (New Haven: Yale University Press,
2013), 83.
[15] The claim that
forms are “in” their instances is a contested claim in Plato studies. Plenty of
scholars would defend it, but it is not universally agreed. See, for instance,
Daniel Devereux, “Separation and Immanence in Plato’s Theory of Forms,” in Gail
Fine (ed.), Plato 1: Metaphysics and
Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, 192–214. Some
postulate metaphysical entities intermediate between forms and particulars. For
example, Allan Silverman distinguishes between forms and form-copies (or
forms-in-things). See, Silverman, The
Dialectic of Essence.
[16] On the claim
that sensible things really are good,
beautiful, just, etc., see Alexander Nehamas, “Plato on the Imperfection of the
Sensible World,” in Gail Fine (ed.), Plato
1: Metaphysics and Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999,
171–91.
[17] What
he calls “really real reality” (ousia
ontôs ousa) in Phd. 247c,
“completely real” (pantelôs on) and
“purely real” (eilikrinôs on) in Rep. 477–79, and “perfectly real” (teleôs on) and “really real” (ontôs on) in Rep. 597.
[18] See Gregory
Vlastos, “Degrees of Reality in Plato,” in R. M. Bambrough (ed.), New Essays on Plato and Aristotle (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965), 1–19.
[19] The
relation of forms and particulars is not symmetrical. It is not unintelligible
to think of forms without particulars, but particulars cannot be anything at
all without forms—the notion of particulars without forms is literally unthinkable. (Thus, strictly speaking,
philosophical materialism is an impossible
notion to a Platonist.) So particulars depend on forms in order to be, but
forms do not depend on particulars. Whether or not this means that forms could
exist without necessarily being instantiated is a different issue. Plato may or
may not have thought that forms have to be instantiated in particulars at some
point in time. Gail Fine argues that Socrates takes no stand on the issue
either way. See Gail Fine, “Separation,” Oxford
Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2 (1984) 31–87.
[20] The
myths that Plato uses can lead readers to take his comments in literal terms.
He will talk in terms of ascending to “the place above the sky” (Phd. 247), for instance. But he very
clearly flags his myths as myths,
heuristic stories that are not to be taken at face value (e.g., Phd. 265c). The notion of the forms
existing in a realm outside the cosmos is a
myth, not to be taken literally. The same can possibly be said about the
notion of knowledge of the forms as “recollection” of what we knew in an
earlier disincarnate life. The heart of the story is not about the literal
reality of disembodied life but rather the claim that “the truth of beings is already in the soul” and hence knowledge
of it is non-empirical (Meno 86b).
“The capacity for knowledge is innate in each man’s mind” (Rep. 518c). On this interpretation of knowledge-as-recollection,
see Perl, Thinking Being, section 6.
[21] Jacob Howland, The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy
(Philadelphia: Paul Dry, 2004), 127, 131.
[22] Gail
Fine has cogently argued against the two worlds interpretation of Platonic
epistemology (“Knowledge and Belief in Republic
5–7,” in Gail Fine [ed.], Plato 1:
Metaphysics and Epistemology, 215–46). According to the two
worlds interpretation, Plato believed that one can only know the forms, so
there can be no knowledge of the
sensible world, only belief. This
account would flatly contradict the Meno,
in which we are told that knowledge is true belief bound by an “explanatory
account” (aitias logismos) (98a).
According to the two worlds account, Plato believed that nobody could know that, say, any specific person or
deed is just—one could only ever have beliefs
about such things. Fine argues that the Republic
itself, the basis on which the two worlds interpretation tries to get off the
ground, fails to provide the support that it needs. After all, the good rule of
the philosophers is predicated on their knowledge of the forms and their ability to bring that to bear in
the world. Furthermore, the Republic
states that it is possible to have beliefs about forms (506c) and knowledge of
sensibles (520c). Fine makes the case that Plato “argues only that all
knowledge requires (not that it is restricted to) knowledge of Forms; and that,
restricted to sensibles, one can at most achieve belief. This, however, leaves
open the possibility that, once one knows Forms, one can apply this knowledge
to sensibles so as to know them too” (ibid., 216). When a person is a prisoner
in the cave, seeing only shadows, then he has no knowledge, not even of what he
sees. At best he has belief. But when he ascends from the cave to gaze at the
sun, he knows the Good, and when he returns to the cave he knows the sensible things too (Rep. 520c). So there is no unbridgeable chasm between knowledge and
belief, because there is no unbridgeable chasm between forms and particulars.
One can ascend from the lower to the higher cognitive states.
[23]
Schindler, Catholicity of Reason,
126.
[24] In terms of the
story of the cave the philosopher is goaded into his troublesome journey
towards the sun by the realization that the shadows on the wall are merely
projected by humans. Interestingly, the sophist has exactly the same
realization but reacts in the opposite way. He sees nothing beyond the
manipulation of shadows and so spends his time teaching others how to
manipulate shadows to their own advantage. Howland, The Republic, 137–41. The sophist sounds like some contemporary postmoderns: when truth disappears there’s
nothing left but power and manipulation to make things work for us.
[25] The Good (Rep. 505a; 507c–509b; 511b; 516b) is the
ultimate principle of relational unity in realty, “a relational absolute that orders
other universals” (Adrian Pabst, Metaphysics:
The Creation of Hierarchy, [Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2012], 2). It “is
present in forms and [particular] things, positioning them in mutual, real
relations. . . . [T]he Good ‘gives’ itself ecstatically in such a way that it
infuses all things with goodness, and it is this generative presence in
immanent things that enables them to participate in the universal forms and
thus perfect their given goodness” (ibid., 32, 33). “[T]he
Form of the Good is not a distinct Form, but the teleological structure of
things; individual Forms are its parts, and particular sensible objects
instantiate it” (Fine, “Knowledge and Belief in Republic 5–7,” 228). Unlike the forms, “the Good is not ousia but is beyond ousia, exceeding it in dignity and power” (Rep. 509b). Given that it is “beyond being,” what the Good is
“itself by itself” cannot even be thought.
We can only grasp the Good in relation to that which it originates and
illuminates—i.e., the forms. (Note that in Platonic ontology, only forms are
beings—“that which is always real and has no becoming.” Particulars occupy the
metaphysical space between being and nothing—they are “that which is always
becoming, but never has real be-ing” Tim.
28a)
It
ought to be noted that Plato’s ontology is deeply relational. Particulars are
only what they are because they of the way in which they relate to each other
and to the forms in which they participate. Forms themselves are inter-related
and “interweave” in complex ways (Rep.
510b; 511b; 517b-c; 519c-d; 526e; Theat.
206c–208b; Soph. 259e; 263e–264a) and
are themselves in a relation of dependence on the Good. Indeed, “all forms are
in virtue of the ecstatic self-exteriorizing ‘being’ of the Good. . . . [T]he
Good governs all forms and actualizes all particulars” (Pabst, Metaphysics, 44). The binding,
relational source of all is the Good. On Plato’s relational ontology, see Mary
McCabe, Plato’s Individuals
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994); Gail Fine, “Relational
Entities,” in Plato and Knowledge and
Form: Selected Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 326–49;
Pabst, Metaphysics, ch. 1.
Comments
"It was necessary, then, for the copies of the heavenly things to be purified with these sacrifices, but the heavenly things themselves with better sacrifices than these."
At any rate, we're agreed that Plato doesn't see the body as inherently evil, and I imagine he'd say with Saint Paul that 'the splendor of the heavenly bodies is one kind, and the splendor of the earthly bodies is another.'